1 Why People Make ‘Bad’ Choices
According to the late Milton
Friedman and other members of the ‘Chicago School’ of economics we
have to assume that people – except lunatics and children –
rationally pursue their own interests. But a casual observation of
the state of the world suggests that, in fact, most people
are either lunatics or
children, so this does not leave us with a large class of people
whose choices are to be respected.
There is ample evidence from both common
observation (including introspection) and careful professional
psychological studies that many – and probably most, if not all –
people frequently make choices that are not really in their best
interests. (For present purposes I shall define these as ‘bad’
choices although it is arguable that in many cases such choices can
be defended.) Behavioural psychologists have identified various
classes of reasons for such ‘self-defeating’ behaviour. One is that
people simply lack full self-knowledge of their own preferences.
Another is that their strategies are based on an imperfect
recollection, or interpretation, of past experiences in certain
situations. Also, in particular, emotional stress plays a large
part in such behaviour. Under emotional distress, people shift
towards favouring high-risk, high-payoff options, even if these are
objectively poor choices.
Another common cause of self-defeating action is
a concern for social considerations. People may pay too much
attention to what other people think. Or they may get very upset in
response to a blow to their pride, ‘…and the rush to prove
something great about themselves overrides their normal and
rational way of dealing with life’.1 Also a variety of social
considerations tend to lock people into consumption habits and
constrain their freedom of choice, such as class, family, culture,
ideology, national character and so on.2
Thanks to the work of many behavioural
psychologists such as Daniel Kahneman and colleagues, various other
explanations of such behaviour have been proposed. Kahneman
distinguishes between two modes of thinking, namely System 1 and
System 2.3 The latter
comprises a careful reflection and analysis of the available
options. The former relies much more on guesswork, intuition and
previous experience. It saves time and mental energy. People need
some kind of energy to weigh up all the costs and benefits of any
choice and many people do not have it, or have used it up, at some
crucial point.4 But
it means that one is prone to make several mistakes which, as
Kahneman and his colleagues have shown, in many common types of
System 1 thinking, have certain features in common.
One of these is a common tendency to be
optimistic about one’s own capabilities. For example, surveys have
shown that, in the USA, about 80% of motorists think that they are
better drivers than the average. Another common type of mistake is
what is known as the ‘anchoring’ effect. This effect can be seen in
numerous transactions, such as in influencing how much one is
prepared to bid when negotiating to buy a house or a car, where it
is rare to put in a bid very far removed from some initial asking
price.
The ‘endowment’ effect is a further example of
what seem to be inconsistent choices. This is where people value
more highly some object that they happen to own – quite apart from
sentimental attachment and so on – than would be justified by some
objective valuation based on how much they value other objects that
they do not own but that have equal monetary value.
An example of what seem to be inconsistent
choices among highly educated people is recent analysis of the
choices made by a large sample (386) of employees of the highly
respected Boston University. They were all asked their preferences
as regards the way they would like their consumption levels to vary
over their lives, given their existing income prospects. For
example, those who did not care much about a likely severe fall in
consumption levels in old age would save less than those who did.
So their preferred profiles of consumption over their lives had
implications for what their savings and insurance behaviour ought
to be. But when their actual savings and insurance behaviour were
examined it was shown that most of them were far from following the
required strategy. There was, in fact, very little correlation
between their preferred lifetime consumption profiles and those
that would result from their actual savings and insurance
behaviour. And the strategies were just as inconsistent for
high-income professors who had significant financial knowledge as
for low-income staff without such knowledge.5
However, it should not be thought that reliance
on System 2 rather than System 1 for purposes of making choices
always produces more welfare-enhancing outcomes. Indeed, some
studies suggest that even if people are reflective and suffer from
none of the mentioned impediments to Kahneman’s System 2, they
still sometimes make choices that aren’t in their best interests.
For example, some students who were given the time to follow System
2 and reflect on and assess all the attributes of university
courses from which they could choose subsequently made less optimal
course choices than the students who were not asked to reflect much
on the choice. Similarly, other students who were allowed to
reflect carefully on their choices were more influenced by
irrelevant factors – for example, by the way in which the choice
scenarios were framed rather than by the rationality of either
option – than were the other test participants. So we have to face
the fact that even when we have enough mental resources and
motivation to engage in thorough reflection on our choices, we can
still make choices that are not in our best interests.
This is particularly the case in choices
involving the future. For it is generally accepted that people
suffer from what Pigou called ‘defective telescopic faculty’ when
it comes to taking account of future costs and benefits. This is
particularly important since many choices require forecasting
future costs and benefits. Sometimes these involve short-term
pleasures but long-term pains. In such cases if people discount
future costs too heavily they will fail to maximise their welfare
over the relevant time period. Also, in most cases the present
benefits are certain and the future costs are uncertain, which
makes it even more tempting to discount them very heavily. There
are many ways in which failure to take due account of longer-term
consequences leads to decisions that reduce people’s longer term
welfare. Eating too many fattening foods, smoking, drugs,
unprotected sex, excessive drinking, are all examples of this
failure to make choices that maximise one’s welfare over
time.
One real-world implication of an apparent
inconsistency in choice is the experience of some companies’
policies concerning their employees’ contribution to pension
schemes. Instead of leaving it up to employees to make the positive
decision to contribute to their pensions, many companies in the USA
have switched to making the contributions automatic while giving
the employees the right to opt out of the scheme. Thus the scheme
was not paternalistic in the sense of imposing choices on the
employees. Anyway, the result in these cases was a big increase in
employees’ participation in the schemes, and only a few opted out.
In other words, when it was a question of opting in, few took up
the option, which seems to indicate a preference for staying out.
But when it was a case of opting out, few took up the option, which
indicated a preference for staying in. Clearly there is some
inconsistency here with respect to which option employees thought
was in their best interests (Sunstein, 2005, ch. 8). It is true that the different
income effects of the alternative transactions could explain very
small disparities but the large disparities observed go well beyond
that.
Of course, even if people are reflective and
rational and suffer from none of the impediments to Sunstein’s
System 2 thinking mentioned earlier, welfare maximising choice may
be very difficult simply because the options will often seem
incommensurate. At the beginning of this chapter we considered the
conflict between values arising in a student’s choice of career. In
that example there was a conflict between the values of the student
and the values of his parents. But on either side there was no
doubt some conflict of values. The student in question probably
took account of the value that a more lucrative occupation would
permit, such as more appealing cultural activities, including
foreign travel, or going to the opera, not to mention the ability
to eat high-class food washed down with Chateau Mouton Rothschild
claret. If, in the end, he chose a less lucrative career on account
of its inherent interest and so on, this could have been the
outcome of a very difficult choice between conflicting values. And
conflicts of values are ubiquitous at the level both of the
individual and society as a whole.
The general problem of incommensurability of
values, which is one of the main objections to classical
Utilitarianism, is discussed in Chapter
10. Some of the resulting problems in economic
policy are discussed in Chapter
6. But there is one particular conflict of values
that arises directly from the previous discussion of the ways in
which people’s ignorance of the effects of some of their choices
may do them harm. For this raises the question of how far one
should force people to make choices that are believed to be in
their best interests. In other words how far should society trade
off the value of ‘consumer sovereignty’, or ‘personal autonomy’
against paternalism and its accompanying restriction on individual
liberty.
2 Information and ‘Rational Ignorance’
Even when people are not irrational in the manner
described earlier they will still very often make choices that do
not best promote their welfare on account of lack of information.
Lack of information is obviously an all-pervasive feature of most
decisions that people take, ranging from what career path they
embark on to which toothpaste best protects their teeth. This is
particularly the case when the choices involve – as is often the
case – judgements about risk and probabilities. For example, it is
well known that people are far more worried about the probability
of being killed in a railway or aircraft accident than in a road
accident, though the statistical evidence suggests that the latter
probability is much greater.
However, information gaps do not necessarily
indicate a failure to behave rationally. There is what is known as
‘rational ignorance’. Consumers may sometimes lack information
because they have rationally decided that the costs to them – in
terms of time or money – of getting the extra information is not
worth it in terms of the likely pay-off. Consider the following
example that must be replicated in one form or another every day by
thousands of tourists all over the world. Outside the Duomo in
Florence there are kiosks that sell, among other things, postcards
– photographs of the Duomo, or of Michelangelo’s statue of David
after he had slain Goliath, or of some famous Raphael or Botticelli
painting and so on. About a 10-minute walk north of the Duomo, in
the direction of the Piazza Annunziata, there are a couple of
bookshops that sell exactly the same postcards as those outside the
Duomo, but at a much lower price. How is this possible? Quite
simply, coach-loads of tourists are deposited outside the Duomo for
a short time; they take their photographs of the façade and the
adjacent Giotto tower and perhaps the Ghiberti low-reliefs around
the Baptistery outside the Duomo, and then may spend a few minutes
buying postcards from the closest kiosks. It would be uneconomical
for them to waste time walking all around the area in order to
check whether they could save a few cents by buying the same cards
elsewhere. It is this allowance by most people for the costs of
acquiring information that is known as ‘rational ignorance’. By
contrast, most people go to much more trouble to obtain information
when making big investments, such as buying a car, or a house,
where it is worth doing so.
And in some cases the relevant information is
about the future, which is never known to us completely. Lack of
information and inability to predict future tastes and preferences
is amply demonstrated by the high divorce rates. Given high divorce
rates and the assumption that, in most cases, divorce is a
last-resort option, marriage is clearly a gamble. Indeed, I am
surprised that it is still legal. Instead – unlike gambling for
money – it is actively encouraged, unless one is married to more
than one person at a time. At least when one gambles on a horse to
win a race it is possible to study the horse’s past form, including
its record over similar distances and under similar circumstances.
Such information is not usually available for marriage.
Also, while it may often be perfectly rational to
make choices without obtaining all the relevant information,
information is not a commodity like any other commodity. For one
cannot know what is the optimum amount of investment one should
make to obtain information until one already has the information.
So in many cases lack of information probably does cut the link
between preferences and welfare, as when people are not aware that
they need the information or that it is available – for example,
taking a highly paid job unaware that it was likely to be only a
short-term job and that it will not prepare them for subsequent
employment. Not knowing what one needs to know may be particularly
important in certain situations, such as the trade in toxic waste
(discussed in more detail in Chapter
8).
Furthermore, much information has the character
of a public good – that is, that there is no extra marginal cost in
allowing an extra person to have access to a piece of information
once that information is available to other people. It is rather
like a radio or TV broadcast, where once the programme is on the
air, so that some people can enjoy it, there is no further cost in
allowing other people to share in it. It is well known that in a
free market the supply of information in public goods is unlikely
to be optimal. Hence, in the case of many forms of information,
there can be no presumption that people enjoy a socially optimal
amount of it.
3 Consumer Sovereignty or Paternalism?
Given the general scepticism about the crude
‘preference-satisfaction theory of good’, how can individuals’
preference satisfaction be a good starting point for judgements
about social welfare? Most economists recognise that people’s
‘manifest’ preferences (to use Harsanyi’s term), namely the ones
that determine market outcomes, including prices, are often bad
guides to their welfare, for the various reasons enumerated
earlier. Consequently, many economists and philosophers believe
that one should often overrule ‘revealed preferences’ and force or
push consumers into expenditure choices that the authorities
believe would better promote their welfare. In other words,
consumer sovereignty would often give way to paternalism.
There are, of course, innumerable actual examples
of not relying entirely on people’s preferences, including what are
known as ‘merit goods’ (or their counterpart ‘demerit goods’). The
most important example is basic education. Education benefits
partly the community at large, of course, and so has an element of
externality in it that would justify a subsidy even if it were a
purely private good. But some people might still not take advantage
of the opportunity to educate their children more cheaply. They
might prefer to be able to spend more on drink, or a better car, or
a foreign holiday. Thus education is usually made compulsory.
There are many other examples of a paternalist
attitude, as when, for example, regulations are introduced that
prevent people doing harm to themselves on account of the sort of
psychological forces outlined previously. For example, there are
lots of instances where we all accept that public restriction on
freedom of choice is justified, such as prescription medicines,
Health and Safety Regulations, as well as some instances where it
is more debatable – drugs, smoking in public places, fatty foods
and so on.6 And
because people are known to underestimate the probability of their
being involved in a road accident, many people would not wear seat
belts unless they were compulsory (and did not do so for many years
before they were made compulsory). So Parliament decided that
people would have to be made to wear them.
In the defence of such measures it can be argued
that one is not really challenging the validity of people’s ends,
but only helping them to achieve them. In other words, the
objection to such interference with people’s choices reflects a
failure to distinguish between ends and means – that is, society
should not try to interfere with people’s ends, but should be
allowed to correct their errors about the means to achieve them.
For example, one can assume that most people have top-level values
to go on living. But suppose we have good reason to believe that if
they postpone giving up smoking, or dieting and so on, they will
die earlier – that is, we believe that they are failing to promote
their ends. Thus, for example, seat belts in cars, or helmets for
motorcyclists, would support their objective of long life.
However, there is a long-established tradition in
support of the view that people are better judges of their own
interest than are some outside authorities. For example, in his
famous book, On Liberty,
first published in 1859, John Stuart Mill devoted a whole chapter
to the question of the extent to which the authorities should
overrule the preferences of ordinary people, in the course of which
he wrote that
…the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or mental, is not a sufficient warrant. He cannot rightfully be compelled to do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so, because it will make him happier, because, in the option of others, to do so would be wise or even right.
And this view has been echoed by other
philosophers throughout the ages, as, for example, Robert Nozick,
who wrote in 1974 that ‘Two noteworthy implications [of his, i.e.
Nozick’s, view] are that the state may not use its coercive
apparatus for the purpose of getting some citizens to aid others,
or in order to prohibit activities to people for their own good or protection’.7
Of course, Mill – and even Nozick – could not
have been aware of all the modern evidence for believing that
people are not best judges of their own interests. So it is
arguable that they were quite wrong about the basic assumption that
people are the best judges of their interests. On the other hand,
as Robert Sugden has cogently argued, there is not much evidence
that authorities are any better.8 It is highly plausible that in some
cases ‘nanny knows best’, but even in such cases does this really
justify overriding consumers’ preferences in most other cases at
the cost of a probable mistaken belief of what is in their
interests? It would be wrong to assume that the alternative to
reliance on fallible consumers is intervention by some public
authority that is all-seeing, fully informed, efficient, honest,
rational and impartial. Nowhere is the ‘agent-principal’
distinction more important than in most public authorities, where
the principals are the public and the agents are the officials who
have their own agendas.
Furthermore, freedom to choose, even if it may
mean making mistakes, may be an independent top-level value. People
may attach ‘end value’ to freedom to choose even if they know they
may not make the wisest choices. Hence, the objective of maximising
people’s welfare by preventing their free choice in certain
situations may be subordinated to the objective of respect for
their rights.
In any case, one may be reluctant to brush aside
people’s revealed preferences on the grounds that this would be the
first step down a slippery slope via paternalism and
authoritarianism to tyranny. For one has to be aware of the danger
of excessive paternalism. Many tyrannies have been based on the
view that people do not know what is best for them or that, even if
they do, they ought to be motivated by a sense of duty to do what
is best for the society in which they live. A cavalier rejection of
democratic respect for people’s preferences can lead to very
undesirable outcomes, not to mention an unjustified infringement of
people’s liberties.
On the other hand, it can be argued that it is
morally admirable to respect and promote the ‘projects’ (life aims)
of other people because they have value. So a certain amount of
paternalism is justified in order to help them pursue their
objective, even though we may think that they are mistaken in their
beliefs about how to promote their objectives. In other words a
certain amount of paternalism could be defended on the grounds that
it does not represent a challenge to people’s values, but is merely
a way of helping them promote those values.
Again there is no scientific way of trading off
the objective of paternalistic welfare maximisation against the
objective of respect for consumers’ ‘rights’, including their right
to make their own mistakes about the means they adopt to pursue
their ends. Faced with a difficult choice between these conflicting
values, one compromise policy is the ‘nudge approach’ that has been
advocated notably by Thaler and Sunstein.9 In the UK there is now an official
‘nudge unit’, known as ‘The Behavioural Insights Team’, which takes
account of recent academic research into behaviour to devise
‘nudge’ policies that will be of value to people and the community
by making it easier for people to take the decisions that will best
promote their welfare. Most obvious are ‘opt-out against opt-in’
policies for, say, pension schemes. But other ‘nudge’ policies
would include, for example, health warnings on cigarette packaging,
or clear indication of possibly harmful ingredients in some
foodstuffs and so on.
However, even the ‘nudge’ approach is based on
the assumption that people would be better off making choice A
rather than choice B. This is then assumed to justify framing
people’s choices in a way that will increase the chances of their
making choice A, without falling into the paternalist trap of
forcing them to do so. Neither of these assumptions is clearly
compelling. For example, consider the aforementioned example of
obliging employees to opt-out of a pension scheme rather than
having to opt-in, so that the default is membership of the scheme.
It is assumed that people who remain in the scheme but who might
otherwise have failed to opt-in will be better off as a result. But
it is possible that they would have been better off if they had not
joined the pension scheme and had made their own arrangements for
their old age, or even not at all for that matter.
Thus, again, there do not seem to be any
clear-cut answers. In certain cases – such as the availability of
possibly dangerous medicines – the case for paternalism may be very
strong, but the case for restrictions on the consumption of
fattening foods may be less so. The net social welfare gain from
one policy or another may be difficult to access. And even if some
reasonable rough balance sheet can be drawn up, there is still the
problem of balancing the net gain or loss against the violation of
personal liberty.
4 Altruism and Commitment
One important reason why the axioms of
rationality specified earlier do not guarantee that people’s
choices will promote their ‘welfare’ is that some people may
deliberately and consciously choose not to maximise their own
welfare. The welfare that most people expect to derive from their
choices may depend partly on the effect they expect to have on the
welfare of other people. Such modes of behaviour may satisfy the
two axioms of rational choice without being motivated purely by
self-interest. And modern theories of human behaviour in terms of
game theory, particularly their behaviour in repeated games, which
is the situation that people are faced with in society, explicitly
allow for people’s preferences to include considerations such as
altruism. For, over the course of human history, some concern for
the interests of others has helped establish viable societies which
indirectly promote people’s self-interest. In the non-human animal
world ‘reciprocal altruism’, as it has been called in evolutionary
biology, suggests that evolution has led to animals being
programmed to have concern for other animals in proportion to the
probability that the other animals will share their genes. In the
human world it is the social evolutionary process that has
contributed to the development of altruistic considerations in the
human psyche.
The concept of ‘sympathy’, defined widely to
include altruism and a capacity to enjoy other people’s good
fortunes, played a crucial role in the work of Adam Smith and David
Hume. Smith’s Theory of Moral
Sentiments begins with the assertion that, ‘How selfish
however man be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his
nature, which interest him in the fortunes of others, and render
their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from
it, except the pleasure of seeing it’. Smith was not limiting the
concept of ‘sympathy’ to the more common current usage, which
refers to sympathy with the misfortunes of other people. It also
included a more general ability to empathise with other people.
Sympathy and benevolence also play an important role in Hume’s
moral and political theory. He wrote that ‘No quality of human
nature is more remarkable, both in itself and in its consequences,
than that propensity we have to sympathise with others, and to
receive by communication their inclinations and sentiments, however
different from or even contrary to our own’.10
In his famous article ‘Rational Fools: A Critique
of the Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory’, Amartya Sen
distinguishes between his concept of ‘sympathy’ and what he calls
‘commitment’ (Sen, 1982a).
Roughly speaking, sympathy is when you can raise your own welfare
by raising somebody else’s, and commitment is when you reduce your
welfare in order to raise somebody else’s. For Sen, ‘commitment
does involve, in a very real sense, counter-preferential choice,
destroying the crucial assumption that a chosen alternative must be
better than (or at least as good as) the others for the person
choosing it.…’ (Sen, 1982, p.
93).11 Whereas
sympathy can be regarded as a form of altruism for beginners, or
‘elementary altruism’, ‘commitment’ can be regarded as ‘advanced
altruism’ and gives rise to choices that are expected to reduce
one’s own welfare. In both cases one person’s utility function is
dependent partly on another’s.
However, it is doubtful whether this particular
discrepancy between people’s choices and their own welfare
justifies any intervention in the pattern of consumers’
expenditures. The motivations in question – many of which may be
highly commendable – do not necessarily detract from the welfare of
society as a whole. Nor do they call for any revision of basic
economic models of consumer behaviour. They can be seen as being
part of the innumerable influences on the position of consumers’
demand curves in price–quantity space, without violating the
assumption that these curves slope down from left to right in the
normal way. It is not obvious that ‘commitment’ violates this
assumption.
Lionel Robbins stressed this point in his famous
book, The Nature and Significance
of Economic Science. In it he argued that that the economic
theory of how producers and consumers behave is in no way
invalidated by dropping the assumption that homo economicus is some totally
egoistical creature concerned only with the pursuit of his
self-interest. In his book Robbins wrote that ‘…our economic
subjects can be pure egoists, pure altruists, pure ascetics, pure
sensualists or – what is much more likely – bundles of all these
impulses’. He went on to say that ‘Considerations of this sort
enable us to deal also with the oft-repeated accusation that
Economics assumes a world of economic men concerned only with
money-making and self-interest’ (Robbins, 1945 edn:95).
Robbins gives the example of a community that had
been converted from pure hedonism to the objective of devoting
their lives to God. The demand for wine would fall off and the
demand for materials to build more churches, synagogues or mosques
would rise. These changes in demands and supplies and their
consequent changes in relative prices will follow the usual basic
laws of economics. The price of wine would fall, and the price of
the materials needed to build places of worship would rise. Labour
would gradually move out of wine production into the construction
industry. Demand and supply would still rule.
Or consider the more mundane case of Mrs X who,
out of commitment to the survival of small local shops, goes out of
her way to buy apples from a shop near where she lives rather than
from a supermarket, which is cheaper and where there is no cat
sleeping on the meat-slicer. In terms of a simple demand curve in
price–quantity space her demand curve for apples from that
particular shop would be further out to the right than would be
that of some other customer who does not share her ‘commitment’.
But it could still slope down from left to right. For example, if
the shopkeeper raised the price of his apples she might tend to buy
less from him and more from the supermarket, or she may switch from
apples to pears. Indeed, if the shop owner raised the price enough
Mrs X might decide that she need not carry commitment too far and
would stop buying apples from that shop altogether. Thus,
commitment does not make her demand curve for apples from that
particular supplier slope the wrong way. It merely means that it is
further out to the right than it would have been in the absence of
this commitment. There are all sorts of reasons why people’s demand
curves for particular products differ from each other, which are
usually ascribed to differences in incomes and ‘tastes’. This does
not mean that they do not slope downwards from left to right, which
has been well-established in a vast amount of empirical
research.
5 Conclusions
One of the important limitations on the normative
significance of market outcomes is that the choices that people
make in the market do not necessarily really reveal their ‘true’
preferences. And even where they do, their ‘true’ preferences may
not always promote their ‘true’ welfare. There are various reasons
for this, including irrational behaviour, inadequate information
and many other psychological influences on choices other than those
encompassed in conventional economic analysis. Thus while the
assumption that, on the whole, people’s choices will promote their
objectives in a rational manner is fairly compelling, there are
various reasons why these choices may often fail to do so. This
weakens the link between choices and people’s welfare.
Nevertheless, without the assumption that
individuals’ preference orderings correspond fairly closely to
their welfare orderings, welfare economics would not even get off
the ground, let alone fly as far as it has done. For although
welfare economics is not very much concerned with changes in the
welfare of individuals as such for their own sake, welfare
economics does require a criterion of an increase in the welfare of
individuals. This is simply because the welfare of society is
usually seen as a logical construction from the welfare of
individuals. In other words if we use a theoretical model of
micro-economics based on the notion of preference satisfaction in
order to see under what conditions the market will allocate
resources in a way that will best contribute to society’s welfare,
we have to assume that a key variable in the model – namely an
individual’s preferences – does have a fairly close correspondence
to the individual’s welfare.12 If we just throw up our hands and
say ‘Oh well, all we are saying is that people are playing this
game of making choices and ranking alternatives but these have
absolutely nothing to do with their welfare’, the moral
significance of the outcome of the market transactions could no
longer be assessed in terms of its contribution to society’s
economic welfare.
For various reasons,
therefore, the fact that there is strong evidence that, by and
large, people behave in a manner predicted by micro-economic theory
does not mean that the preferences which give rise to this
behaviour reflect their real ‘welfare’. No amount of empirical
evidence can show that it does, since ‘welfare’ is not an objective
concept. The assumption that people’s preferences correspond
approximately to their
welfare may well be justified. But it is important to know why it
is not more than an approximation.
Furthermore, some of the welfare that people
enjoy comes from their sharing in certain activities or duties or
conveying sentiments in a manner for which mere monetary
transactions are inadequate. And as has been argued in recent
important contributions made by Elizabeth Anderson and Michael
Sandel to the problem of the moral limits of the market, this part
of their wider welfare can be destroyed, or misrepresented, by
excessive marketing of certain goods and services. Sandel
emphasizes the manner in which marketing certain goods, such as the
sale of blood for medical purposes, diminishes the moral
significance that voluntary blood donation gives. Elizabeth
Anderson puts more emphasis on the manner in which putting a price
on certain social facilities, such as access to parks, restricts
their value to the personal values of individuals rather than the
social significance of shared facilities. Some marketing procedures
– such as Sandel’s example of the practice of allowing some
prisoners to enjoy special facilities in jail – offend social
notions of the equality with which punishment for crimes should be
meted out irrespective of a person’s financial
circumstances.13
Bibliography
Aldred, J., 2009,
The Skeptical Economist,
Earthscan, London.
Brocas, Isabelle, and
Carrillo, Juan D. (eds.), 2003, The Psychology of Economic Decisions,
Rationality and Well-Being, Oxford University Press.
Conly, S., 2013,
Against Autonomy: Justifying
Coercive Paternalism, Cambridge University Press.
Hausman, D.M., and
McPherson, M.S., 2009, ‘Preference Satisfaction and Welfare
Economics’, Economics and
Philosophy, 25/1.
Hume, D., 1751,
An Enquiry Concerning the
Principles of Morals, 1998 edition, Beauchamp, T. (ed.),
Oxford University Press.
Kahneman, D., 2011,
Thinking, Fast and Slow,
Farrar, Straus and Giroux.
Nozick, R., 1974,
Anarchy, State, and Utopia,
Basic Books, New York, and Blackwell, Oxford.
Offer, A., 2006,
The Challenge of Affluence,
Oxford University Press.
Robbins, L., 1945,
The Nature and Significance of
Economic Science, (2nd edn.), Macmillan, London.
Sen, A., 1982, ‘Equality of
What?’, repr. in Sen, A. (ed.), Choice, Welfare and Measurement,
Blackwell, Oxford.
Sen, A., 1982a,
Rational Fools: A Critique of the
Behavioural Foundations of Economic Theory, reprinted in
Sen, 1982b.
Sen, A., 2009, The Idea of Justice, Alan Lane,
London.
Sugden, R., 2008, ‘Why
Incoherent Preferences do not Justify Paternalism’, Constitutional Political Economy,
19.
Sunstein, C., 2005,
Laws of Fear, Cambridge
University Press.
Thaler, R.H., and Sunstein,
C., 2008, Nudge: Improving
Decisions about Health, Wealth and Happiness, Yale
University Press.
Footnotes
6
The case for autonomy has been recently well set
out in Conly, 2013. She argues
that if Mill had been able to know what modern behavioural
psychologists have brought to light he would have taken a different
view.
11
See also Sen’s later exposition of his
distinction between ‘sympathy’ and ‘commitment’ in Sen,
2009:188–193.
12
A similar conclusion is reached on the basis of a
detailed analysis in Hausman and McPherson, 2009.
13
Anderson, E., Value in Ethics and Economics. Harvard
University Press, 1953; and Sandel, M., What Money Can’t Buy, The Moral Limits of
Markets, Allen Lane, Penguin Books, 2012.