We begin by introducing some basic notation and terminology. Then we discuss relations and, in particular, equivalence relations, which we shall see several times throughout the book. In the final section, we talk about various sorts of functions.
1.1 Sets and Set Operations





But sets do not necessarily consist of numbers. Indeed, we can consider the set of all letters of the alphabet, the set of all polynomials with even integers as coefficients or the set of all lines in the plane with positive slope.
The objects in a set are called its elements. We write if a is an element of a set S. Thus,
but
. The set with no elements is called
the empty set, and denoted
. Any other set is said to be
nonempty.
If S
and T are sets, then we
say that S is a subset of T, and write , if every element of S is also an element of T. Of course,
. We say that S is a proper subset of T, and write
, if
but
. Thus, it is certainly true that
, but we can be more precise and write
.
For any two
sets S and T, their intersection, , is the set of all elements that lie
in S and T simultaneously.
Example 1.1.
Let and
. Then
.
We can extend this notion to the
intersection of an arbitrary collection of sets. If I is a nonempty set and, for each
, we have a set
, then we write
for the set of elements that lie in
all of the
simultaneously.
Example 1.2.
For each , let
. Then
.
Also, for any
sets S and T, their union, , is the set of all elements that lie
in S or T (or both).
Example 1.3.

Furthermore, if I is a nonempty set and we have a set
for each
, then we write
for the union of all of the
; that is, the set of all elements
that lie in at least one of the
.
Example 1.4.
If we use the same sets as in Example 1.2, we have
.
In addition, for any two sets S and T, the set difference (or relative complement) is the set
.
Example 1.5.
Once again using S and T as in Example 1.1, we have .
We will need one more definition. The following construction is named after René Descartes.
Definition 1.1.
Let S and T be any sets.
Then the Cartesian
product is the set of all ordered pairs
(s, t), with
and
.
Example 1.6.



There is also a Cartesian product of
finitely many sets. For any sets , we let
be the set of all ordered n-tuples
, with
for all i.
Example 1.7.





Exercises
1.1.
Let and
. Find
,
,
,
and
.
1.2.
Let ,
and
. Find
,
,
,
and
.
1.3.
Let R, S
and T be sets with . Show that
.
1.4.
Let , for some positive integer n. Show that S has
subsets.
1.5.
Let R, S
and T be any sets. Show that
.
1.6.
For each positive integer n, let .
- 1.
What is
?
- 2.
What is
?
1.2 Relations
We are going to use relations (in particular, the equivalence relations and functions that we will see in the next two sections) quite a few times in this course.
Definition 1.2.
Let S and T be sets. Then
a relation from
S to T is a subset of
. If
and
, then we write
if
; otherwise, we write
. In particular, a relation on S is a relation from S to S.
Example 1.8.
Let and
. Define a relation
from S to T via
if and only if
. Then
. In particular,
but
.
We will focus on relations on a set. Let us discuss a few properties enjoyed by some relations.
Definition 1.3.
Let be a relation on S. We say that
is reflexive if
for all
.
Example 1.9.
On , the relation
is reflexive, but < is not.
Indeed,
for all integers a, but 1 is not less than 1.
Definition 1.4.
A relation on a set
S is symmetric if
implies
.
Example 1.10.
On , neither
nor < is symmetric, as
but 2 is not less than 1 (and
similarly for
). Define
via
if and only if
. Then
is symmetric. Indeed, if
, then
, and so
; thus,
.
Definition 1.5.
Let be a relation on a set
S. We say that
is transitive if, whenever
and
, we also have
.
Example 1.11.
On , the relations
and < are both transitive. (If
and
, then
.) However, the relation
from Example 1.10 is not, since
and
, but
.
These three properties lead us directly to the next section.
Exercises
1.7.
Let and
. Define a relation
from S to T via
if and only if
. Find all pairs
such that
.
1.8.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if ab is even. Is
reflexive? Symmetric? Transitive?
1.9.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if
. Is
reflexive? Symmetric? Transitive?
1.10.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if
. Is
reflexive? Symmetric? Transitive?
1.11.
- 1.
How many relations are there on
?
- 2.
How many of these relations are symmetric?
1.12.
For each of the eight subsets of
, find a relation on
that has the properties in that
subset, but not the properties that are not in the subset.
1.3 Equivalence Relations
Definition 1.6.
An equivalence relation on a set S is a relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive.
We will use the symbol to denote an equivalence
relation.
Example 1.12.
On , let us say that
if and only if
is even. We claim that
is an equivalence relation. If
, then
is certainly even, so
, and
is reflexive. If
, then
is even. But this also means that
is even, and hence
. Thus,
is symmetric. Finally, suppose that
and
. Then
and
are both even. This means that their
sum,
, is even. As 2b is even, we see that
is even, and hence
. That is,
is transitive.
Example 1.13.
On the set , let
if and only if
for some
. Let us verify that this is an
equivalence relation. Reflexivity: Note that
, and hence
. Symmetry: If
, say
, then
, and hence
. Transitivity: If
and
, say
and
, then
, and therefore
.
Example 1.14.
On , let us say that
if and only if
. Let us check that it is an
equivalence relation. Reflexivity: If
, then
, and hence
. Symmetry: Let
. Then
, and hence
. Thus,
. Transitivity: Suppose that
and
. Then
, and hence
. That is,
.
Let us try something slightly more complicated.
Example 1.15.
Let . Define
on S via
if and only if
. We must verify that
is an equivalence relation.
Reflexivity: As
, we have
for all integers a and nonzero integers b. Symmetry: Suppose that
. Then
, and this also tells us that
. Transitivity: Let
and
. Then
and
. Thus,
. Since we are assuming that
, this means that
. Therefore,
.
Equivalence relations are very special.
Definition 1.7.
Let be an equivalence relation on a set S. If
, then the equivalence class of a, denoted [a], is the set
.
Why are equivalence classes so interesting? We need another definition.
Definition 1.8.
Let S be a set, and let T be a set of
nonempty subsets of S. We say
that T is a partition of S if every lies in exactly one set in T.
Example 1.16.
Let and
. Then T is a partition of S.
What is the connection between these concepts?
Theorem 1.1.
Let S be a set, and an equivalence relation on S. Then the equivalence classes with
respect to
form a partition of S. In particular, if
, then
and, furthermore,
if and only if
.
Proof.
As is reflexive,
, and hence
for every
. In particular, the equivalence
classes are not empty, and every element of S is in at least one of them. Suppose
that
. We must show that
. If
, then
. Also,
means that
, and hence
by symmetry. Also,
. By transitivity,
, and then
. Thus,
, and therefore
. By the same argument,
, and hence
. Thus, the equivalence classes do
indeed form a partition. To prove the final statement of the
theorem, note that if
, then
and, conversely, if
, then
.
So, the equivalence classes break the
set down into subsets having no elements in common. It is important
to note that, unless there is only one element in an equivalence
class, the representative chosen for that class is not unique. That
is, if , then we could just as easily write
[b] instead of [a]. They are the same class. This
complicates matters a bit when we define operations on equivalence
classes, as we will find ourselves doing throughout the course. We
must make sure that our operations are well-defined; that is, that
they do not depend upon the particular representative of the class
that we use.
Let us discuss the equivalence classes determined by the relations in our earlier examples. The plan is always the same. We know that each element of the set is in exactly one class. Thus, we will keep looking for elements of the set that are not in any classes we have constructed, and obtain new classes in this way.
Example 1.17.

![$$[0]=\{\ldots ,-6,-4,-2,0,2,4,6,\ldots \}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ7.png)
![$$14\in [0]$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_IEq254.png)
![$$[0]=[14]$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_IEq255.png)


![$$[1]=\{\ldots ,-5,-3,-1,1,3,5,\ldots \}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ8.png)
![$$[-3]$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_IEq258.png)

Example 1.18.
![$$[1]=\{1,2,4,8,16\}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ9.png)
![$$[3]=\{3,6,12\}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ10.png)
![$$[5]=\{5,10,20\}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ11.png)
![$$\begin{aligned}\ [7]&=\{7,14\},\ [9]=\{9,18\},\ [11]=\{11\},\\ [13]&=\{13\}, [15]=\{15\},[17]=\{17\},\text { and }[19]=\{19\}.\end{aligned}$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ12.png)
The other two examples are a bit trickier, since there are infinitely many equivalence classes. But we can attempt to describe them.
Example 1.19.
![$$b\in [a]$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_IEq260.png)
![$$[23.86]=\{\ldots ,-2.14,-1.14,-0.14,0.86,1.86,2.86,\ldots \}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ13.png)










![$$[b]\ne [c]$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_IEq271.png)
![$$\{[b]:b\in \mathbb R,\ 0\le b<1\}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ14.png)
Example 1.20.
![$$(c,d)\in [(a, b)]$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_IEq272.png)








![$$[(2,3)]=\{\ldots ,(-6,-9),(-4,-6),(-2,-3),(2,3),(4,6),(6,9),\ldots \}.$$](/epubstore/L/G-T-Lee/Abstract-Algebra/OEBPS/images/429924_1_En_1_Chapter/429924_1_En_1_Chapter_TeX_Equ15.png)
Exercises
1.13.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if
, for some
. Is
an equivalence relation? If so, what
are the equivalence classes?
1.14.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if a and b are both even or both odd. Is
an equivalence relation? If so, what
are the equivalence classes?
1.15.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if
. Is
an equivalence relation? If so, what
are the equivalence classes?
1.16.
Define a relation on
via
if and only if
. Is
an equivalence relation? If so, what
are the equivalence classes?
1.17.
Let S be the set of all subsets of
. Define a relation
on S via
if and only if
. Is
an equivalence relation? If so, what
are the equivalence classes?
1.18.
Let S be the set of all subsets of
. Define a relation
on S via
if and only if
and
are both finite. Show that
is an equivalence relation and
describe
and
.
1.19.
On the plane , define a relation
via
if and only if
. Show that
is an equivalence relation, and
describe [(4, 2)].
1.20.
Let S be a nonempty set. Show that for any partition of S, there is an equivalence relation on S having the sets in the partition as its equivalence classes.
1.21.
Find an equivalence relation on
having exactly two equivalence
classes, one of which contains exactly three elements.
1.22.
Suppose there is a relation on a set S, such that
is both reflexive and transitive.
Define
on S via
if and only if
and
. Show that
is an equivalence relation.
1.4 Functions
Let us give two equivalent definitions
of a function. Formally, if S
and T are sets, then a function
from S to T is a relation from S to T such that, for each
, there is exactly one
such that
. In practice, nobody really thinks of
functions in this way. The working definition follows.
Definition 1.9.
Let S and T be any sets.
Then a function
is a rule assigning, to each
, an element
of T.
Readers who have studied calculus will
no doubt be familiar with functions from to
.
Example 1.21.
We can define a function via
for all
.
But we do not need to go from
to
.
Example 1.22.
We can define a function via
for all
.
In fact, the sets involved do not have to be sets of numbers.
Example 1.23.
Let S be the set of all English words and
T the set of letters in the
alphabet. We can define by letting
be the first letter of the word
w, for every
.
A few properties enjoyed by certain functions are important.
Definition 1.10.
A function
is one-to-one (or injective)
if
implies
, for all
.
Putting this another way, a one-to-one function sends different elements to different places.
Example 1.24.
Define functions and
from
to
via
and
, for all
. Then
is not one-to-one, since
, but
is one-to-one, since if
, then taking the cube root of both
sides, we have
, for any
.
Definition 1.11.
A function is onto (or surjective) if, for every
, there
exists at least
one
such that
.
Example 1.25.
Define and
as in Example 1.24. Then
is not onto, since there is no
such that
. However, if
, then
; thus,
is onto.
We should not get the idea that one-to-one and onto always occur together.
Example 1.26.
Define via
. Then
is one-to-one, for if
, then taking the base 2 logarithm of
both sides, we see that
. On the other hand, there is no
such that
, so
is not onto.
However, it is nice when we can combine the two properties.
Definition 1.12.
A function is bijective if it is one-to-one and
onto.
An equivalent way of expressing this
property is that for each , there is exactly one
such that
. There must be such an s, since
is onto, but if
, for some
, then since
is one-to-one,
. For this
reason, a bijective function is also known as a one-to-one correspondence.
Let us discuss how to combine functions.
Definition 1.13.
Let R, S
and T be sets, and let
and
be functions. Then the composition,
, or simply
, is the function from R to T given by
for all
.
Note that when we write , we are applying
first, then
. The order is important! Indeed,
depending upon the sets involved, it is possible that applying
first, then
, would not make sense. But even if it
did make sense, the result would not necessarily be the same.
Example 1.28.
Define functions and
from
to
via
and
, for all
. Then
, whereas
, for all
. That is,
and
are different functions.
We can list a few important properties of the composition of functions.
Theorem 1.2.



- 1.
;
- 2.
if
and
are one-to-one, then so is
;
- 3.
if
and
are onto, then so is
; and
- 4.
if
and
are bijective, then so is
.
Proof.
(1) Take any . Then
. Similarly,
.
(2) Suppose that for some
. Then
. Since
is one-to-one,
. Since
is one-to-one,
.
(3) Take any . Since
is onto, there exists an
such that
. But
is also onto, so there exists an
such that
. Thus,
.
(4) Combine (2) and
(3).
The following additional property of bijective functions can be useful.
Theorem 1.3.
Let be a bijective function. Then there
exists a bijective function
such that
for all
and
for all
.
Proof.




















Example 1.29.
Let be given by
for all a. Example 1.27 showed us that
is bijective. It is easily checked
that if we let
be given by
for all a, then
for all a.
We close the chapter by defining two special types of functions.
Definition 1.14.
A permutation of a set S is a bijective function from S to S.
Example 1.30.
By Example 1.27, the function
given by
is a permutation of
.
Example 1.31.
Let . Define
via
,
,
and
. Then
is a permutation of S.
As this last example illustrates, a permutation is simply a rearrangement of the elements of S.
Definition 1.15.
Let S be a set. Then a binary operation on S is a function
from to S.
Example 1.32.
We can define a binary operation
on
via
, for all
. (Putting this in terms of functions,
we could write
for all
.)
Note that in order to obtain a binary
operation, we must stay within our original set. For instance, we
would not get a binary operation on if we tried to let
, for the simple reason that
.
Exercises
1.23.
Define via
. Is this function one-to-one? Is it
onto?
1.24.
Define via
. Is this function one-to-one? Is it
onto?
1.25.
Let S be the set of real numbers and
T the set of positive real
numbers. Define via
. Show that
is a bijection and find
such that
for all
.
1.26.






1.27.

- 1.
- 2.
- 3.
for all a and b
1.28.
Let S be a finite set, and suppose that
is a one-to-one function. Show that
is a permutation of S. Construct an explicit counterexample
to show that this need not be true if S is infinite.
1.29.
Let and
be functions, and suppose that
is onto. Must
be onto? Must
?
1.30.
Let and
be functions, and suppose that
is one-to-one. Must
be one-to-one? Must
?
1.31.
Let S be a set with m elements and T a set with n elements, for some positive integers m and n.
- 1.
How many functions are there from S to T?
- 2.
How many of these functions are one-to-one?
1.32.
Let S and T be sets and a function. Show that there exist a
set R and functions
and
such that
is onto,
is one-to-one and
.